Fundamental theorem of arithmetic

In number theory and algebraic number theory, the Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic (or Unique-Prime-Factorization Theorem) states that any integer greater than 1 can be written as a unique product (up to ordering of the factors) of prime numbers. For example,

6936 = 2^3 \times 3 \times 17^2 , \,\!
1200 = 2^4 \times 3 \times 5^2 . \,\!

are two examples of numbers satisfying the hypothesis of the theorem that can be written as the product of prime numbers. Intuitively, this theorem characterizes prime numbers uniquely in the sense that they are the "fundamental numbers."

Proof of existence of a prime factorization is straightforward: proof of uniqueness is more challenging. Some proofs use the fact that if a prime number p divides the product of two natural numbers a and b, then p divides either a or b, a statement known as Euclid's lemma. Since multiplication on the integers is both commutative and associative, it does not matter in what way we write a number greater than 1 as the product of primes; it is generally common to write the (prime) factors in the order of smallest to largest.

Some natural extensions of the hypothesis of this theorem allow any non-zero integer to be expressed as the product of "prime numbers" and "invertibles". For example, 1 and -1 are allowed to be factors of such representations (although they are not considered to be prime). In this way, one can extend the Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic to any Euclidean domain or principal ideal domain bearing in mind certain alterations to the hypothesis of the theorem. A ring in which the Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic holds is called a unique factorization domain.

Many authors assume 1 to be a natural number that has no prime factorization. Thus Theorem 1 of Hardy & Wright (1979) takes the form, "Every positive integer, except 1, is a product of primes," and Theorem 2 (their "Fundamental") asserts uniqueness. By convention, the number 1 is not itself prime, but since it is the product of no numbers, it is often convenient to include it in the theorem by the empty product rule. (See, for example, Calculating the gcd.)

Contents

Applications

The fundamental theorem of arithmetic establishes the importance of prime numbers. Prime numbers are the basic building blocks of any positive integer, in the sense that each positive integer can be constructed from the product of primes with one unique construction. Finding the prime factorization of an integer allows derivation of all its divisors, both prime and non-prime.

For example, the above factorization of 6936 shows that any positive divisor of 6936 must have the form 2a × 3b  × 17c, where a takes one of the 4 values in {0, 1, 2, 3}, where b takes one of the 2 values in {0, 1}, and where c takes one of the 3 values in {0, 1, 2}. Multiplying the numbers of independent options together produces a total of 4 × 2 × 3 = 24 positive divisors.

Once the prime factorizations of two numbers are known, their greatest common divisor and least common multiple can be found quickly. For instance, from the above it is shown that the greatest common divisor of 6936 and 1200 is 23 × 3 = 24. However, if the prime factorizations are not known, the use of the Euclidean algorithm generally requires much less calculation than factoring the two numbers.

The fundamental theorem ensures that additive and multiplicative arithmetic functions are completely determined by their values on the powers of prime numbers.

Proof

The theorem was practically proved by Euclid (in book 7 of Euclid's elements, propositions 30 and 32), but the first full and correct proof is found in the Disquisitiones Arithmeticae by Carl Friedrich Gauss. It may be important to note that Egyptians like Ahmes used earlier practical aspects of the factoring, such as the lowest common multiple, allowing a long tradition to develop, as formalized by Euclid, and rigorously proven by Gauss.

Although at first sight the theorem seems 'obvious', it does not hold in more general number systems, including many rings of algebraic integers. This was first pointed out by Ernst Kummer in 1843, in his work on Fermat's Last Theorem. The recognition of this failure is one of the earliest developments in algebraic number theory.

Euclid's proof (of existence)

The proof consists of two steps. In the first step every number is shown to be a product of zero or more primes. In the second, the proof shows that any two representations may be unified into a single representation.

Non-prime composite numbers

Suppose there were positive integers which cannot be written as a product of primes. Then there must be a smallest such number (see well-order): let it be n. This number n cannot be 1, because of the empty-product convention above. It cannot be a prime number either, since any prime number is a product of a single prime, itself. So it must be a composite number. Thus

n = a \cdot b .

where both a and b are positive integers smaller than n. Since n is the smallest number which cannot be written as a product of primes, both a and b can be written as products of primes. But then

n = a \cdot b .

can be written as a product of primes as well, simply by combining the factorizations of a and b; this is a proof by contradiction. This is a minimal counterexample argument.

Proof of uniqueness

The key step in proving uniqueness is Euclid's proposition 30 of book 7 (known as Euclid's lemma), which states that, for any prime number p and any natural numbers a, b: if p divides ab then p divides a or p divides b.

This may be proved as follows:

A proof of the uniqueness of the prime factorization of a given integer proceeds as follows. Let s be the smallest natural number that can be written as (at least) two different products of prime numbers. Denote these two factorizations of s as p1···pm and q 1···qn, such that s = p1p2···pm = q 1q2···qn. Both q1 and q 2···qn must have unique prime factorizations (since both are smaller than s). By Euclid's proposition either p1 divides q1, or p1 divides q 2···qn. Therefore p1  =  qj (for some j).[1] But by removing p1 and qj from the initial equivalence we have a smaller integer factorizable in two ways, contradicting our initial assumption. Therefore there can be no such s, and all natural numbers have a unique prime factorization.

Alternate proof

Assume that s is the least integer that can be written as (at least) two different products of prime numbers. Denote these two factorizations of s as p1···pm and q 1···qn, such that s = p1p2···pm = q1q2···qn.

No pi (with 1 ≤ i ≤ m) can be equal to any qj (with 1 ≤ j ≤ n), as there would otherwise be a smaller integer factorizable in two ways (by removing prime factors common in both products), violating the above assumption. Now it can be assumed without loss of generality that p1 is a prime factor smaller than any q j (with 1 ≤ j ≤ n). Let d be the quotient and r the remainder from dividing q 1 by p1. By the division algorithm d and r are guaranteed to be integers such that q 1 = dp1 + r and 0 ≤ r < p1. Note immediately that since q 1 is prime it cannot be a multiple of p1 and thus

r \neq 0.\!

Also, since q1 is greater than p1

d \ge 1.\!

Substituting in for q1 in the original definition of s above,

s = p_1 p_2\cdots p_m = (dp_1 + r) q_2\cdots q_n.\!

By distributivity:

s = p_1 p_2\cdots p_m = d p_1 q_2\cdots q_n + r q_2\cdots q_n.\!

Define a new integer k = s −dp1q2···qn = rq2···qn. Since d≥ 1, it is clear that k must be smaller than s. And since r>0, k must be positive. From the definition of k, it follows that:

k = p_1 p_2\cdots p_m - d p_1 q_2\cdots q_n\!

and by factoring out p1:

k = p_1 (p_2\cdots p_m - d  q_2\cdots q_n).\!

Therefore there is a prime factorization of k that includes p1. But it is also true that

k = r q_2\cdots q_n.\!

Since r < p1, p1 cannot be a prime factor of r. Thus, by combining the prime factors of r with q2···qn, it is also possible to construct a prime factorization of k that does not include p1. Therefore k has two different prime factorizations, which contradicts the original assumption that s is the least such number. Therefore, no numbers with two different prime factorizations can exist.

Generalizations

The Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic generalizes to various contexts; for example in the context of ring theory, where the field of algebraic number theory develops. A ring is said to be a unique factorization domain if the Fundamental theorem of arithmetic (for non-zero elements) holds there. For example, any Euclidean domain or principal ideal domain is necessarily a unique factorization domain. Specifically, a field is trivially a unique factorization domain.

Notes

  1. If p1 divides q1 then, since both are prime, p1 = q1. If, on the other hand, p1 divides q 2···qn, then, since p1 and all 'qn are prime, and we know that q 2···qn has a unique prime factorization, then p1 must be among q 2···qn.

See also

References

External links